home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
- --------
- Nos. 90-1205 and 90-6588
- --------
- UNITED STATES, PETITIONER
- 90-1205 v.
- KIRK FORDICE, GOVERNOR OF MISSISSIPPI, et al.
-
- JAKE AYERS, et al., PETITIONERS
- 90-6588 v.
- KIRK FORDICE, GOVERNOR OF MISSISSIPPI, et al.
- on writs of certiorari to the united states court of
- appeals for the fifth circuit
- [June 26, 1992]
-
- Justice Thomas, concurring.
- ``We must rally to the defense of our schools. We must
- repudiate this unbearable assumption of the right to kill
- institutions unless they conform to one narrow standard.''
- W.E.B. Du Bois, Schools, 13 The Crisis 111, 112 (1917).
- I agree with the Court that a State does not satisfy its
- obligation to dismantle a dual system of higher education
- merely by adopting race-neutral policies for the future
- administration of that system. Today, we hold that ``[i]f
- policies traceable to the de jure system are still in force and
- have discriminatory effects, those policies too must be
- reformed to the extent practicable and consistent with
- sound educational policies.'' Ante, at 10. I agree that this
- statement defines the appropriate standard to apply in the
- higher-education context. I write separately to emphasize
- that this standard is far different from the one adopted to
- govern the grade-school context in Green v. New Kent
- County School Bd., 391 U. S. 430 (1968), and its progeny.
- In particular, because it does not compel the elimination of
- all observed racial imbalance, it portends neither the
- destruction of historically black colleges nor the severing of
- those institutions from their distinctive histories and
- traditions.
- In Green, we held that the adoption of a freedom-of-choice
- plan does not satisfy the obligations of a formerly de jure
- grade-school system should the plan fail to decrease, if not
- eliminate, the racial imbalance within that system. See id.,
- at 441. Although racial imbalance does not itself establish
- a violation of the Constitution, our decisions following
- Green indulged the presumption, often irrebuttable in
- practice, that a presently observed imbalance has been
- proximately caused by intentional state action during the
- prior de jure era. See, e.g., Dayton Bd. of Ed. v. Brinkman,
- 443 U. S. 526, 537 (1979); Keyes v. School Dist. No. 1,
- Denver, Colo., 413 U. S. 189, 211 (1973). As a result, we
- have repeatedly authorized the district courts to reassign
- students, despite the operation of facially neutral assign-
- ment policies, in order to eliminate or decrease observed
- racial imbalances. See, e.g., Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklen-
- burg Board of Ed., 402 U. S. 1, 22-31 (1971); Green, supra,
- at 442, n. 6.
- Whatever the merit of this approach in the grade-school
- context, it is quite plainly not the approach that we adopt
- today to govern the higher-education context. We explicitly
- reject the use of remedies as ``radical'' as student reassign-
- ment-i.e., ``remedies akin to those upheld in Green.'' Ante,
- at 10, n. 4; see also ante, at 9. Of necessity, then, we
- focus on the specific policies alleged to produce racial
- imbalance, rather than on the imbalance itself. Thus, a
- plaintiff cannot obtain relief merely by identifying a
- persistent racial imbalance, because the district court
- cannot provide a reassignment remedy designed to elimi-
- nate that imbalance directly. Plaintiffs are likely to be able
- to identify, as these plaintiffs have identified, specific
- policies traceable to the de jure era that continue to produce
- a current racial imbalance. As a practical matter, then, the
- district courts administering our standard will spend their
- time determining whether such policies have been ade-
- quately justified-a far narrower, more manageable task
- than that imposed under Green.
- A challenged policy does not survive under the standard
- we announce today if it began during the prior de jure era,
- produces adverse impacts, and persists without sound
- educational justification. When each of these elements has
- been met, I believe, we are justified in not requiring proof
- of a present specific intent to discriminate. It is safe to
- assume that a policy adopted during the de jure era, if it
- produces segregative effects, reflects a discriminatory
- intent. As long as that intent remains, of course, such a
- policy cannot continue. And given an initially tainted
- policy, it is eminently reasonable to make the State bear
- the risk of nonpersuasion with respect to intent at some
- future time, both because the State has created the dispute
- through its own prior unlawful conduct, see, e.g., Keyes,
- supra, at 209-210, and because discriminatory intent does
- tend to persist through time, see, e.g., Hazelwood School
- Dist. v. United States, 433 U. S. 299, 309-310, n. 15 (1977).
- Although we do not formulate our standard in terms of a
- burden shift with respect to intent, the factors we do
- consider-the historical background of the policy, the degree
- of its adverse impact, and the plausibility of any justifica-
- tion asserted in its defense-are precisely those factors that
- go into determining intent under Washington v. Davis, 426
- U. S. 229 (1976). See, e.g., Arlington Heights v. Metropoli-
- tan Housing Development Corp., 429 U. S. 252, 266-267
- (1977). Thus, if a policy remains in force, without adequate
- justification and despite tainted roots and segregative
- effect, it appears clear-clear enough to presume conclu-
- sively-that the State has failed to disprove discriminatory
- intent.
- We have no occasion to elaborate upon what constitutes
- an adequate justification. Under Green, we have recognized
- that an otherwise unconstitutional policy may be justified
- if it serves ``important and legitimate ends,'' Dayton, supra,
- at 538, or if its elimination is not ``practicable,'' Board of
- Ed. of Oklahoma City v. Dowell, 498 U. S. ___, ___ (1991)
- (slip. op., at 11). As Justice Scalia points out, see post, at
- 5-6, our standard appears to mirror these formulations
- rather closely. Nonetheless, I find most encouraging the
- Court's emphasis on ``sound educational practices,'' ante, at
- 10 (emphasis added); see also, e.g., ante, at 12 (``sound
- educational justification''); ante, at 17 (``sound educational
- policy''). From the beginning, we have recognized that
- desegregation remedies cannot be designed to ensure the
- elimination of any remnant at any price, but rather must
- display ``a practical flexibility'' and ``a facility for adjusting
- and reconciling public and private needs.'' Brown v. Board
- of Ed., 349 U. S. 294, 300 (1955). Quite obviously, one
- compelling need to be considered is the educational need of
- the present and future students in the Mississippi univer-
- sity system, for whose benefit the remedies will be crafted.
- In particular, we do not foreclose the possibility that
- there exists ``sound educational justification'' for maintain-
- ing historically black colleges as such. Despite the shame-
- ful history of state-enforced segregation, these institutions
- have survived and flourished. Indeed, they have expanded
- as opportunities for blacks to enter historically white
- institutions have expanded. Between 1954 and 1980, for
- example, enrollment at historically black colleges increased
- from 70,000 to 200,000 students, while degrees awarded
- increased from 13,000 to 32,000. See S. Hill, National
- Center for Education Statistics, The Traditionally Black
- Institutions of Higher Education 1860 to 1982, pp. xiv-xv
- (1985). These accomplishments have not gone unnoticed:
- ``The colleges founded for Negroes are both a source of
- pride to blacks who have attended them and a source
- of hope to black families who want the benefits of
- higher learning for their children. They have exercised
- leadership in developing educational opportunities for
- young blacks at all levels of instruction, and, especially
- in the South, they are still regarded as key institutions
- for enhancing the general quality of the lives of black
- Americans.'' Carnegie Commission on Higher Educa-
- tion, From Isolation to Mainstream: Problems of the
- Colleges Founded for Negroes 11 (1971).
- I think it undisputable that these institutions have
- succeeded in part because of their distinctive histories and
- traditions; for many, historically black colleges have become
- ``a symbol of the highest attainments of black culture.'' J.
- Preer, Lawyers v. Educators: Black Colleges and Desegre-
- gation in Public Higher Education 2 (1982). Obviously, a
- State cannot maintain such traditions by closing particular
- institutions, historically white or historically black, to
- particular racial groups. Nonetheless, it hardly follows that
- a State cannot operate a diverse assortment of institu-
- tions-including historically black institutions-open to all
- on a race-neutral basis, but with established traditions and
- programs that might disproportionately appeal to one race
- or another. No one, I imagine, would argue that such
- institutional diversity is without ``sound educational
- justification,'' or that it is even remotely akin to program
- duplication, which is designed to separate the races for the
- sake of separating the races. The Court at least hints at
- the importance of this value when it distinguishes Green in
- part on the ground that colleges and universities ``are not
- fungible.'' Ante, at 9. Although I agree that a State is not
- constitutionally required to maintain its historically black
- institutions as such, see ante, at 23-24, I do not understand
- our opinion to hold that a State is forbidden from doing so.
- It would be ironic, to say the least, if the institutions that
- sustained blacks during segregation were themselves
- destroyed in an effort to combat its vestiges.
-